Lara's Term Paper: Difference between revisions

From Lexical Resource Semantics
Jump to navigation Jump to search
No edit summary
Line 34: Line 34:
=== Logical Quantifiers (Generalized Quantifiers) ===
=== Logical Quantifiers (Generalized Quantifiers) ===


<span style="color:#00CC00">T A B E L L E</span>
[[File:Logical-quantifiers.png|Logical Quantifiers]]
 
 


=== The Universal Quantifier ∀ ===
=== The Universal Quantifier ∀ ===

Revision as of 21:20, 23 June 2016

Introduction to Quantifiers

The following e-learning material provides an introduction to the topic of quantifiers by integrating examples, illustrations as well as different types of interactive exercises of varying difficulty and their solutions. It intends to cover the central ideas of the concept of quantifiers without too much formal logic and therefore provides a basis for further study.

Author: Lara

(Back to the Group Overview or Hauptseminar: "New Media in Teaching Semantics")


Wiki pages

Definition

A ‘quantifier’ is a word like many, few, little, several, which is used in a noun phrase to indicate the quantity of something.

In logic, quantifiers are operators binding variables, which means that a quantifier connects parts of a sentence that classify a domain of discourse.

Individual variables are written as “x” and can refer to any individual.


Different Types of Quantifiers

There are different types of quantifiers which can be divided in:

  • Logical quantifiers
    • Universal quantifier
    • Existential quantifier
  • Restricted quantifiers

In predicate logic the two fundamental quantifiers are the logical quantifiers (also called generalized quantifiers), which are the universal quantifier and the existential quantifier.


Logical Quantifiers (Generalized Quantifiers)

Logical Quantifiers

The Universal Quantifier ∀

  • The universal quantifier is used to mean that the statement is true for every entity in the domain in question.
  • symbolized by the operator ∀
  • conveyed by such expressions as all, every and each
  • The sequence “∀x” is read as
    • “For every thing x”
    • “For any value of x”
    • “For all values of x”
    • “Whatever x may be”


EXAMPLES

The following examples show quantified sentences translated into predicate logic formulae.


Every dog is barking.

∀x (DOG (x) → BARK (x))

“For every thing x, if x is a dog then x is barking.”


All students were tired.

∀x (STUDENT (x) → TIRED (x))

“For every thing x, if x is a student then x is tired.”


NOCH EIN BEISPIEL


NOCH EIN BEISPIEL


Negation:


No trains are late.

Wherever you put an x, this statement does not hold:

∀x ~ (TRAIN (x) → LATE (x))

“It is not the case that for all x, if x is a train then x is late.”

Or equivalently, we can use the existential quantifier (see below) and say:

There is no x for which this statement would hold:

~ ∃x (TRAIN (x) & LATE (x))

“There is no x such that x is a train and x is late.”


The Existential Quantifier ∃

  • The existential quantifier is used to mean that the statement is true of at least one entity in the domain.
  • symbolized by the operator ∃
  • stands for expressions with a/an (one), some and there is
  • The sequence “∃x” is read as
    • “There is an x”
    • “There is at least one thing x”

Negation:

  • The special case of the determiner no(ne) is analyzed with ∃ and negation.
  • The sequence “~∃x” (same as “¬∃x”) is read as
    • “There is no x”


EXAMPLES

The following examples show quantified sentences translated into predicate logic formulae.


A dog barked.

∃x (DOG (x) & BARK (x))

“There is at least one thing x such that x is a dog and x barked.”


Anna bought some trashy paperbacks.

∃x (PAPERBACK (x) & TRASHY (x) & BUY (Anna, x))

∃x (PAPERBACK (x) & TRASHY (x) & BUY (a, x))

Note: In the second formula the variable a stands for ‘Anna’. Both of the writings are correct.

“There is an x such that x is a paperback and x is trashy and x is bought by Anna.”


Negation:


No trains are late.

There is no x for which this statement would hold:

~ ∃x (TRAIN (x) & LATE (x))

“There is no x such that x is a train and x is late.”

Or equivalently, we can use the universal quantifier (see above) and say:

Wherever you put an x, this statement does not hold:

∀x ~ (TRAIN (x) → LATE (x))

“It is not the case that for all x, if x is a train then x is late.”


There is no antidote to cyanide.

~ ∃x (ANTIDOTE (x, c))

„It is not the case that there is an x such that x is an antidote to cyanide.“ or „There is no x such that x is an antidote to cyanide.“


Clive ate nothing.

~ ∃x (EAT (c, x))

„There is no x such that Clive ate x.“


Clive didn’t eat one thing.

∃x ~ (EAT (c, x))

„There is at least one thing x such that Clive didn’t eat x.“


The Restricted Quantifier

In contrast to the logical quantifiers …

  • a restricted quantifier always has a reference quantity and therefore points out a proportion of a set and not the proportion of everything there is.
  • Since common natural language quantifiers like most, few, many or several cannot be analyzed like the logical quantifiers in the standard form of the predicate calculus, they are expressed in the notation of restricted quantification.
  • Sentences which contain restricted quantifiers are written with square brackets. This means that the noun phrase including the quantifier is always put into square brackets. Logical quantifiers can also be written in this kind of formula with square brackets.
  • Examples: a few – some – several – many – most – all – every – a – a number – one/two/three – little – no – no one – someone


EXAMPLES

The following examples show quantified sentences translated into predicate logic formulae.


Several cars crashed.

[Several x: CAR (x)] CRASH (x)


Maria peeled and quartered three apples.

[Three x: APPLE (x)] PEEL (m, x) & QUARTER (m, x)


Morris showed Jane every fingerprint he dusted.

[Every x: FINGERPRINT (x) & DUST (m, x)] SHOW (m, x, j)


Most travellers entering or leaving Australia visit Sydney.

[Most x: TRAVELLER (x) & (ENTER (x, a) or LEAVE (x, a))] VISIT (x, s)

[Most x: TRAVELLER (x) & (ENTER (x, a) V LEAVE (x, a))] VISIT (x, s)

Note: In the second formula the logical operator V means ‘or’. Both writings are correct.


Negation:


No dogs barked.

[No x: DOG (x)] BARK (x)


Venn Diagrams

  • Generalized quantifiers can be treated as denoting a relation between two sets and can be illustrated by Venn diagrams.
  • Two sets behave differently with respect to the necessity of being restricted.


Representation of the basic quantifiers all (every), some (one), no(ne) in Venn diagrams:

D R A W I N G: every / all, one / some and no(ne)

In these diagrams, crosses are used to mark the presence of individuals in sets. Effectively the crosses play the role of variables – something which can stand in for any individual.


EXAMPLE

a. All Australians are sportspeople.

DRAWING

∀x (AUSTRALIANS (x) → SPORTSPERSON (x))

All denotes the subset relation between two sets – in the example given, the set of Australians and the set of sportsmen.


b. Some Australians are sportspeople.

DRAWING

Intersection

∃x (AUSTRALIAN (x) & SPORTSPERSON (x))


c. No Australians are sportspeople.

DRAWING

No intersection

There is no x for which this statement would hold:

~ ∃x (AUSTRALIAN (x) & SPORTSPERSON (x))

“There is no x, such that x is an Australian and x is a sportsperson.”

Or equivalently, we can say:

Wherever you put an x, this statement does not hold:

∀x ~ (AUSTRALIANS (x) → SPORTSPERSON (x))

“It is not the case that for all x, if x is an Australian then x is a sportsperson.”


Representation of numerals in Venn diagrams:

Each numeral denotes a relation between sets such that the intersection contains the specific number of objects.


EXAMPLE

a. Five planets are visible to the naked eye.

Here it is indicated that there are five objects which are both planets and are visible to the naked eye. In other words the set of planets and the set of things which are visible to the naked eye have an intersection, and that intersection contains exactly five elements.

DRAWING



Scopal Ambiguity

Scopal ambiguity arises when a sentence contains two or more quantifiers. If this is the case the sentence can be understood in different ways.

Example: Some man loves every woman.




Glossary entries

Links to additionally created glossary entries


Online excercises

Links to additionally created online exercises